Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive
1. The problem 1.1. The IPP effect in active contexts The Continental West-Germanic languages (Dutch, Afrikaans, German and many of their dialects, but not Frisian; see section 4, below, on this variation) are famous for a peculiar morphosyntactic phenomenon manifesting itself in triverbal periphrastic perfects in which the complement of the auxiliary selects an infinitive: in such contexts, the complement of the auxiliary may (in the case of ‘to’-infinitives) or even must (in the case of ‘bare’ infinitives) be shorn of the past-participial morphology that one would have expected to see under the auxiliary. We see this in (1) and (2). (Here and throughout, ‘unexpected’ infinitives will be printed in boldface, for easy spotting; their corresponding participles will be printed in italics.) (1)
a. * hij he b. hij he
had had had had
het the het the
boek book boek book
gewild lezen want.PTC read lezen willen want.IPP/wanted.PTC read
(2)
a.
had had had had
het the het the
boek book boek book
geprobeerd te lezen try.PTC to read proberen te lezen try.IPP to read
b.
hij he hij he
This is known in the literature as the infinitivus-pro-participio effect — ‘IPP’ for short (whence the glosses of willen and proberen in (1b) and (2b)). English does not show this effect in its counterparts to examples in (1) and (2): the b– examples in (3) and (4) are crashingly bad. (3)
a. he had wanted to read the book b. * he had want to read the book
(4)
a.
he had tried to read the book
The Even Yearbook 13 (2018), Department of English Linguistics, Eötvös Loránd University, Budapest ISSN 2061–490X, http://seas3.elte.hu/even. © 2018, Marcel den Dikken
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 2
b. * he had try to read the book To say that English does not feature an IPP effect at all would be too categorical a claim, however. Consider the English example in (5) up close. The orthography of read in (5) hides an interesting twist in this example. As Emonds (1976:115) has noted, there is a difference between the first and second conjuncts in the form of the main verb: in the first conjunct, it is the past-participial form, pronounced /rɛd/; but in the second, read can be pronounced /riːd/, like the infinitive.1 (5)
he says that he has read the book, and read the book, he has
The examples in (6) and (7), featuring verbs whose infinitives and past participles are spelt differently, bring this out directly in the orthography. (6)
he says that he has taken these pictures, and taken/take these pictures, he has
(7)
he says that he has fixed the car, and fixed/fix the car, he has
1
Breul (2014) notes that the IPP version of VP topicalisation examples is in fact more widely attested in corpora than the participial one. Nonetheless, there clearly is variation, both among speakers and between individual cases. A reviewer finds many of the VP topicalisation examples with IPP questionable, and points out that with certain verbs the result is particularly woeful: (i) he said that he had been there, and {beenbɪ/). Similarly, truncation of the participle /dʌn/ done in (ii) via removal of /n/ would produce an illformed surface form (*/dʌ/). This is probably what causes (i) and (ii) to be impossible with IPP. For the examples given in the main text, truncation of the participle by dropping participial morphology does not deliver illicit surface forms; so these cases are kosher. The reviewer also notes that in the presence of certain material preceding the verb of the topicalised VP, IPP becomes impossible as well: (iii) is the reviewer’s example. I have not had a chance to examine this effect in any detail, so I cannot say anything about the range of preverbal elements that have this effect. But for the particular case of only in (iii), I suspect that the ban on IPP can be understood from the perspective of Thoms & Walkden’s (2018) proposal, discussed in section 2, below: the focus particle only needs to be construed with the Foc head (in clause-internal position here: there is no subject–aux inversion in (iii)), which precludes an ellipsis derivation (which would have procured IPP), leaving only a derivation involving movement (which delivers a participle). (iii) he said that he had only taken these pictures, and only {taken/*take} these pictures, he had
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 3
This is an infinitivus-pro-participio (IPP) effect of sorts (see also Kayne 2005:99 for an assimilation of the infinitival cases in (5)–(7) to Continental West-Germanic IPP), apparently brought about by topicalisation of the complement of the auxiliary of the perfect, has. While English does not give rise to an IPP effect in its equivalents to the Dutch examples in (1b) and (2b), Dutch in its turn shows no IPP effect in its counterparts to the English examples in (5), (6), and (7) — regardless of whether the entire VP (8b) or just the verb (8c) is fronted, there must be a participle in the examples in (8): (8)
a. hij heeft het boek niet gelezen/*lezen he has the book not read.PTC/read.IPP b. het boek gelezen/*lezen heeft hij niet the book read.PTC/read.IPP has he not c. gelezen/*lezen heeft hij het boek niet read.PTC/read.IPP has he the book not
Not only does the fronted verb show no IPP, the VP-fronting process even bleeds IPP on the middle verb in triverbal constructions of the type in (1) and (2) when only the projection of the most deeply embedded verb is fronted, as we see in (9):2 (9)
a. het boek lezen heeft hij altijd the book read.INF has he always b. het boek (te) lezen heeft hij nog the book to read has he yet geprobeerd/*proberen try.PTC/try.IPP
gewild/*willen want.PTC/want.IPP nooit never
However, when the projection of the middle verb (the equivalent of English want or try) is fronted, stranding just the auxiliary of the perfect, IPP does manifest itself — as before, optionally in the case of te-infinitives and obligatory with ‘bare’ infinitives: (10) a. het boek willen/ *gewild lezen heeft hij altijd the book want.IPP/want.PTC read.INF has he always
2
In Dutch cases of topicalisation of the complement of verbs like proberen ‘try’, which normally select only te-infinitives, the infinitival marker te can be dropped, as shown in (9b) (Zwart 1993:263; for some speakers, the present author included, dropping te is the preferred option).
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 4
b. het boek proberen/geprobeerd te lezen heeft hij nog the book try.IPP/try.PTC to read.INF has he yet nooit never 1.2. The IPP effect in passive contexts The IPP effect is usually studied only in active contexts. For a comprehensive picture, it is important to include the passive voice as well, because differences present themselves in the realm of IPP between active and passive constructions, in both Dutch and English,. Let me begin again with Dutch. For the modal examples in (1), there are no grammatical passive counterparts, probably for the same reason that English he wanted to read the book does not passivise (*the book was wanted to be read (by him)). But we can check the effect of passivisation on triverbal constructions with a bare infinitive in the most deeply embedded position by looking at laten ‘let’ causatives. The passive examples in (12) (corresponding to the active laten-causatives in (11)) are rarely discussed in the literature, probably because (12) is not generally accepted in Dutch. Coopmans (1985) reports examples of the type in (12a) as acceptable in his Dutch, but other speakers (the present author included) find (12a) rather marginal. There is no blanket ban on passives of laten-causatives, however: the idiomatic example in (12b), the impersonal-passive counterpart to (11b), sounds perfectly fine; plenty of tokens of this type are attested on the internet (as a simple search for the string zijn laten vallen will show; the subject of such examples is almost invariably steken or its diminutive steekjes).3 3
Some attested examples featuring the idiom steken/steekjes laten vallen (as well as one involving a different laten vallen idiom, corresponding to English drop or dump in their figurative sense) are included in (i). In (ii), I list some non-idiomatic tokens of the zijn laten vallen string (which to my ear generally sound somewhat less good than those in (i), but are still squarely within the realm of the acceptable). (i) a. een klein minpunt is de productie, waar toch een paar steekjes bij zijn laten vallen a small minus-point is the production where yet a few stitches-DIM with are let drop b. het is een hele grote verantwoordelijkheid waarin wat steekjes zijn laten vallen it is a very big responsibility wherein some stitches-DIM are let drop c. als er in één zaak in de hele justitieketen zoveel steken zijn laten vallen if there in one case in the whole justice-chain so-many stitches are let drop d. dat er ook bij de onzichtbare afwerking steken zijn laten vallen that there also with the invisible finishing stitches are let drop e. een prachtig boek dat je laat inzien dat er heel wat steken zijn laten vallen bij onderzoeken a beautiful book that you let realise that there quite some stitches are let fall in researches f. ik weet dat sommigen van jullie verschrikkelijk zijn laten vallen door jullie ouders I know that some of you terribly are let drop by your parents (ii) a. dit zijn voorwerpen die door de persoon die is weggelopen zijn laten vallen this are objects that by the person that is away-run are let drop
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 5
(11) a. ze hebben het boek laten/*gelaten lezen they have the book let.IPP/let.PTC read.INF ‘they have had the book read’ b. ze hebben steken laten/*gelaten vallen they have stitches let.IPP/let.PTC drop.INF ‘they have made mistakes’ (12) a. % het boek is laten/*gelaten lezen the book is let.IPP/let.PTC read.INF ‘people were given the chance to read the book’ b. er zijn steken laten/*gelaten vallen there are stitches let.IPP/let.PTC drop.INF ‘mistakes have been made’ In passive (12) the infinitivus-pro-participio effect is just as much in evidence as it is in the active sentences in (11): the form of the causative verb is the bare infinitive laten; using not past-participial gelaten is ungrammatical in both (11) and (12). Fronting the projection of the causative verb preserves the IPP effect (see (13b)), similarly to what we see in active (13a) (cf. (10)).4 laten/*gelaten let.IPP/let.PTC nooit never b. % laten/*gelaten let.IPP/let.PTC
(13) a.
4
lezen hebben ze het boek nog read.INF have they the book yet
lezen is het boek nog nooit read.INF is the book yet never
b. het diertje moet door een kraai of reiger in onze tuin zijn laten vallen the animal-dim must by a crow or heron in our garden be let drop c. verdenkingen tegen haar zijn laten vallen suspicions against her are let drop d. de proefpersoon wordt beoordeeld op tijd, bloedverlies en nietjes die zijn laten vallen the test-person becomes judged on time blood-loss and staples that are let drop Peculiarly, topicalisation of the projection of the most deeply embedded verb fails regardless of the form of the causative verb — both in the active and in the passive (see (i)). This is not due to a general ban on topicalisation of the complement of causative laten ‘let’: when laten is finite, the result is grammatical (see (ii)). This restriction on VP-fronting in causative constructions is not something that I will try to provide an account for here. (i) a. *lezen hebben ze het boek nog nooit laten/gelaten read.INF have they the book yet never let.IPP/let.PTC b. *lezen is het boek nog nooit laten/gelaten read.INF is the book yet never let.IPP/let.PTC (ii) lezen laten ze het boek niet read.INF let they the book not
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 6
Let us turn next to the te-infinitives in (2). Rather marginally (and subject to speaker variation), a ‘long passive’ based on (2) is possible (see Wurmbrand 2001 and others for discussion of such constructions in German). But interestingly, while active (2) offers the speaker of Dutch a choice between a participle and an IPP-infinitive, to the extent that it works (14) is possible only without IPP. (14) % het boek is geprobeerd/*proberen te the book is try.PTC/try.IPP to ‘people tried to read the book’
lezen read.INF
The contrast between (12) (where IPP remains obligatory under passivisation) and (14) (where IPP becomes impossible where it used to be optional in the active) is remarkable. The ill-formedness of (14) with infinitival proberen suggests that passivisation can influence the distribution of IPP. In English we see an effect of voice on IPP as well — in fact, more directly, thanks to the fact that the English examples to follow are not from the rather marginal and speaker-variable underworld. In the English passives in (15)–(17), we find no IPP effect induced by VP-topicalisation, in contrast to what we saw in the active examples in (6)–(8): read in (15b) is pronounced /rɛd/, not /riːd/; and leaving out the participial morphology in (16b) and (17b) is impossible. (15) a. this book has certainly been read by many b. read by many, this book certainly has been (16) a. these pictures have certainly been taken by him b. taken/*take by him, these pictures certainly have been (17) a. the car probably has been fixed by now b. fixed/*fix by now, the car probably has been 1.3. The explananda The distribution of past participles and infinitives in periphrastic perfect and passive contexts in Dutch and English presents us with the following explananda: ➀
Dutch triverbal constructions of the type in (18), with a bare infinitive in the most deeply embedded position: a. obligatory IPP in the ACTIVE voice without VP-fronting — (1), (11)
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 7
b. obligatory IPP in the active voice with fronting of the projection of V2 — (10a) c. illicit IPP in the active voice with fronting of the projection of V3 — (9a) d. obligatory IPP in the passive voice — (12) (18)
[V1=aux [V2 [V3]]]
➁
Dutch triverbal constructions of the type in (19), with a te-infinitive in the most deeply embedded position: a. optional IPP in the active voice without VP-fronting — (2) b. optional IPP in the active voice with fronting of the projection of V2 — (10b) c. illicit IPP in the active voice with fronting of the projection of V3 — (9b) d. illicit IPP in the passive voice — (14)
(19)
[V1=aux [V2 [te V3]]]
➂
VP-fronting constructions involving the complement of auxiliary have/be: a. optional IPP in the active voice in English but illicit IPP in Dutch — (5)–(7) vs (8) b. illicit IPP in the English passive voice — (15)–(17)
The remainder of this paper is about trying to shed explanatory light on these explananda. I will begin by tackling the third problem set.
2. English IPP: Thoms & Walkden (2018) In a thought-provoking and empirically rich paper, Thoms & Walkden (2018) argue that VP-fronting can in principle come about in two different ways in syntax: (a) via a garden-variety instance of movement, or (b) via basegeneration cum ellipsis. The derivation in (a) is of course entirely straightforward, and requires no particular defence in the context of mainstream generative linguistics. Suffice it to make just one essential remark about it: derivations employing (a) MUST feature a total identity relation between the moved constituent and the copy left behind in the position of the PF-gap. For the derivation in (b), this identity condition is looser — and it is here that Thoms & Walkden find their explanation for the difference between our (5)–(7), on the one hand, and (15)–(17), on the other.
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 8
The examples in (5)–(7) with an infinitive instead of the expected past participle can be derived along the lines of the derivation in (b) (which I am simplifying in this paper for expository purposes; the interested reader is referred to Thoms & Walkden’s work for details glossed over here), with either a bare-infinitival or a participial VP base-generated in topic position, linked to an elliptical participial VP in the complement of the auxiliary of the perfect: (20) [VP fixed/fix the car] he has [VP <fixed the car>] Thoms & Walkden support their hypothesis that (5)–(7) with an initial infinitive can be derived with an appeal to ellipsis on the basis of the observation that a bare-infinitival VP can independently be shown to be able to license ellipsis of a past-participial VP in active periphrastic perfects, as in: (21) A: B:
she didn’t lose her temper she has TOO <lost her temper>
And interestingly, Thoms & Walkden point out such a mismatch is illegitimate passive contexts:5 (22) A: John didn’t penalise Molly unfairly B: * she was TOO <penalised unfairly> This, in turn, explains why the variants of (15)–(17) with an infinitive in lieu of a past participle are ungrammatical: such sentences can be derived neither via (a) (because of the absence of total identity between the topicalised VP and the copy in the gap position) nor via (b) (in view of (22)); so there is no path towards deriving the infinitival versions of passive (15)–(17), whereas the
5
I modified Thoms & Walkden’s example (54) (reproduced below as (i)) to eliminate a confound noted by a reviewer of my paper: in (i) the modal introduces a complication that also renders active (ii) ungrammatical. (iB) and (iiB) are ungrammatical for independent reasons (perhaps prosodic in nature) having to do with the distribution of TOO: in the absence of TOO, with verum focus on the modal, both examples are fine; and in VP-fronting constructions, the presence of a modal makes no difference either: see (iii). Dropping the modal from (i) delivers (22) in the main text, which makes Thoms & Walkden’s point without confounds. (i) A: John won’t penalise Molly unfairly B: *she will TOO be <penalised unfairly> (ii) A: she won’t have lost her temper B: *she will TOO have <lost her temper> (iii) he thinks he must have taken these pictures, and {taken/take} these pictures, he must have indeed
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 9
infinitival versions of active (5)–(7) can be derived along the lines of (b), given the grammaticality of (21).
3. No VP ellipsis of the complement of aspectual auxiliaries in Dutch Thoms & Walkden (2018) do not say much about Continental WestGermanic, and what little they say about German (in terms of scrambling) may not generalise to Dutch because Dutch, although it certainly has scrambling, is much less prolific in its range of scrambling options than is German. But Thoms & Walkden’s approach to the English facts actually gives them an excellent handle on the Dutch (and German) data (entirely independently of scrambling), once we remind ourselves of a major difference between Dutch/German and English in the realm of ellipsis phenomena. While the English auxiliaries have and be liberally allow ellipsis of their complements, such VP ellipsis is generally impossible in Dutch (and German; illustration will only be provided for Dutch, as before, for space reasons): (23) a. Bob has read this book, and Peter (has) , too b. this book was read by Bob, and that book (was) , too (24) a. Bob heeft dit boek gelezen, en Peter (*heeft) ook Bob has this book read and Peter has too b. dit boek is door Bob gelezen, en dat boek (*is) ook this book is by Bob read and that book is too Stripping the second conjunct down to just its subject and too/ook is grammatical in both languages. English also allows VP ellipsis in the complement of the auxiliaries have and be, but Dutch does not. The answer to the question of why Dutch cannot mimic English in fronting a bare-infinitival VP in constructions featuring an auxiliary selecting a participle (recall (8)) is now obvious. Since Dutch does not allow VP ellipsis in the complement of the auxiliary for independent reasons, it cannot avail itself in VP-fronting constructions of an ellipsis-based derivation along the lines of (20). If the palette of options is restricted to (a) movement and (b) base-generation cum ellipsis (as Thoms & Walkden assume), then the unavailability of (b) in Dutch confines the language to a movement-based derivation.6 Movement forces complete identity between the fronted VP and 6
Left-dislocation with a d-word resumptive, as in (i), can be recast as an instantiation of the (b) scenario: Thoms & Walkden’s (2018) analysis postulates a null operator in the left periphery of the clause alongside the VP base-generated there; the d-word can be thought of as the lexicalisation of
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 10
the silent copy in the position of the gap. Since the latter is necessarily participial (because it is the complement of a participle-selecting auxiliary), this delivers the desired result that only the participial variants of (8) are grammatical. This now completes the discussion of the third cluster of explananda listed in section 1.3: VP-fronting constructions involving the complement of auxiliary have/be: a. optional IPP in the active voice in English but not in Dutch — (5)–(7) vs (8) b. illicit IPP in the English passive voice — (15)–(17)
➂
4. Dutch IPP: The morphosyntax of the past participle Two sets of explananda remain on the agenda, both addressing Dutch: ➀ and ➁. In this section, I will start by presenting an outlook on the roots of the IPP effect in Dutch in which the prefix ge- of past participles plays a central role. I will subsequently account for the explananda in ➀, involving triverbal constructions with a ‘bare’ infinitive as the most deeply embedded verb, as in (18) (repeated below). The problems in ➁ will be left for section 5. (18) [V1=AUX [V2 [V3]]] 4.1. The morphosyntax of the past participle and the IPP form in Dutch A key empirical observation about the distribution of the IPP effect in Continental West-Germanic is that it strongly tends to occur only in those dialects whose past participles are generally formed with the help of the prefix ge- (see Vanden Wyngaerd 1994, Zwart 2011:310, and references to the earlier literature cited there).7 Frisian and the Stellingwerf dialect are two examples of varieties that systematically lack ge- and also lack IPP; standard Dutch, on the other hand, as a rule features ge- on its past participles and exhibits the IPP effect. this operator.
(i)
a. b.
7
het boek gelezen/*lezen dat the book read.PTC/read.IPP that gelezen/*lezen dat heeft hij he read.PTC/read.IPP that has
heeft hij niet has he not het boek niet t he book not
Hoekstra & Taanman (1995) point out that in the Westfries dialect ge- does not occur on past participles yet IPP is found nonetheless. They attribute this to influence from the standard language.
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 11
There is some noise in this generalisation (apart from what was mentioned in fn. 6): for a sizable set of verbs, the past participle in standard Dutch does not host ge-. The prefix ge- is consistently incompatible with stressless inseparable particles and the prefix her- ‘re-’, so verbs hosting one of these elements to the left of the stem cannot form their past participle with ge-. In (25b–d) we see a triple of cases involving the verb leven ‘live’ which illustrates the general pattern: (25) a. b. c. d.
INFINITIVE
PAST PARTICIPLE
leven ‘live’ her-leven ‘relive’ be-leven ‘experience’ over-leven ‘survive’
(*ge-)her-leef-d (*ge-)be-leef-d (*ge-)over-leef-d
But these exceptions to the general rule that the past participle of standard Dutch is formed with the help of the prefix ge- are immaterial for the discussion of the IPP effect: no verb prefixed with her- or a stressless particle can serve as V2 in the structure in (18) (for reasons that will actually follow from the discussion of (29), below); since V2 is the undergoer of IPP, we can safely set verbs of the type in (25b–d) aside for now (although I will return to them a bit later in this subsection). Verbs that can serve as V2 in the schema in (18) are the modals (which in Dutch have full inflectional paradigms, unlike their English counterparts), the causative/permissive verb laten ‘let’, the perception verbs horen ‘hear’, voelen ‘feel’ and zien ‘see’, and the aspectual auxiliary zijn ‘be’ — this last one occurs as V2 only in the perfect of constructions of the type illustrated by ik ben vissen ‘I am away fishing’: ik ben wezen vissen ‘I have been away fishing’. In (26) I present the morphological forms relevant for our discussion of IPP.8 (26)
CITATION INFINITIVE
a. durven ‘dare’ 8
PAST PARTICIPLE
IPP FORM
durven
For the modal zullen ‘will (future)’, I did not enter a form for the past participle because to my knowledge there is no context in which zullen fails to take a bare-VP complement, and (partial) topicalisation of the bare VP in the complement of zullen is also quite impossible in the perfect (see (i)). Hence in the periphrastic perfect zullen always occurs in the IPP form. The past participle for zullen can readily be formed based on the general morphological rule (ge-zul-d; see (i)); but since it does not occur, I have left it out. (i) a. hij had het boek zullen/*gezuld lezen hij had the book will.IPP/will.PTC read.INF b. *het boek lezen had hij zullen/gezuld c. *lezen had hij het boek zullen/gezuld
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 12
hoeven ‘need’ kunnen ‘can’ moeten ‘must’ mogen ‘may’ willen ‘want’ zullen ‘will (future)’ b. laten ‘let/make’ c. horen ‘hear’ voelen ‘feel’ zien ‘see’ d. zijn ‘be’
—
hoeven kunnen moeten mogen willen zullen laten horen voelen zien wezen/*zijn
I included a separate column for the IPP form because one of the verbs in the set of IPP undergoers has a form in IPP contexts that is different from its citation infinitive: the auxiliary zijn ‘be’ shows up as wezen (cf. Old English wesan ‘be’) when it is V2 in the schema in (18). As an infinitive, the form wezen occurs in present-day Dutch only as a substandard variant of zijn, in the informal vernacular (see (27)); wezen is obsolete as a normal infinitive of ‘be’ in the standard language. je niet zijn/wezen (27) dat wil that want you not be ‘you don’t want to be like that’ The fact that wezen does occur in the standard language as an IPP form thus suggests that the IPP form is not ‘just’ an infinitive. Even though for all other verbs in the set in (26) the IPP form is identical with the citation infinitive, the case of zijn/wezen suggests that the term infinitivus pro participio is actually a misnomer: the substitute for the participle is not in fact the infinitive but a form based on the participial stem (wees in the case of (26d); see also fn. 1, above). Throughout, the IPP form, which like the past participles in the middle column occurs in the complement of an auxiliary that ordinarily selects a participial element, lacks the ge- prefix that is obligatory on the past participle. For a subset of the verbs in (36), leaving off ge- immediately delivers the IPP form — this is true for the five verbs (hoeven, moeten, mogen, laten, zien) whose past participles have the suffix -en, identical with the infinitival suffix. For all other verbs, the alveolar suffix (-d, -t) of their past participles disappears in the IPP form along with ge-, and is replaced with -en. It is primarily for this reason that the regular past participial inflection of Dutch is usually characterised as a circumfix, ge-+-d/t. I will represent the component
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 13
parts of this circumfix separately in the syntax, by treating the suffixal portion as the exponent of an aspectual head (Asp) outside the projection of the verb, and the prefixal portion (ge-) as a particle originating in the complement of the verb. The structure in (28) sums this up: (28)
[V1=AUX [AspP Asp=PTC.SUFFIX [V2 [PrtP Prt=ge-]]]]
In the following paragraphs, I will elucidate this approach, and mobilise it to explain the IPP effect. Inspired by Vanden Wyngaerd (1994), I would like to argue that the key to the IPP effect is the prefix ge- — more precisely, the fact that this prefix is systematically omitted on V2 in the schema in (18). This not only helps us understand the fact that IPP occurs only in varieties of Continental WestGermanic that feature ge- but also gives us a handle on the IPP form of zijn in (26d), whose stem is the same as that of the past participle. IPP syntactically involves the omission of ge-. In the PF component (at spell-out), ge- takes the alveolar suffix of regular past participles down with it in its fall — more precisely, the exponent of ‘PTC.SUFFIX’ in (28) can only be the alveolar -d/-t if the prefixal particle ge- is also present (this is part of the suffix’s vocabulary insertion rule); since in IPP contexts, ge- cannot appear, this immediately blocks -d/-t from occurring as the exponent of Asp. Asp must get exponed, however: a bare stem is unacceptable in the context in which V2 finds itself in (18). With -d/-t out of the competition in IPP contexts, Asp will then be spelled out by the other allomorph of the participial suffix, -en, whose distribution (probably because of syncretism with the infinitival suffix) is not sensitive to the presence of ge-. This is how we get from ge-wees-t /xəʋeːst/ to wez-en /ʋeːzə/ in (26d). If the key to the syntax of the IPP effect in Continental West-Germanic is ge-, then how does ge- work and why is it forced to be absent on V2 in (18)? Here it is important to return for a moment to (25), where we saw that ge- is in complementary distribution with unstressed particles and the prefix her- ‘re-’. For the latter, Keyser & Roeper (1992) argue that it is a verbal particle that occupies a position in the syntax that is autonomous vis-à-vis the verb, with the verb and the prefix coming together as a result of an incorporation process. For unstressed particles like be- in (25c) and over- in (25d), such a treatment is also plausible (see Hoekstra et al. 1987 for be-), especially so in light of the fact that over doubles as a free-standing particle (see Den Dikken 2003 for discussion). Den Dikken (1995) argues at length that particles of the Germanic type (as in put the book down, throw the rubbish out, look the number up) are the syntactic heads of a phrase that finds itself in the immediate complement of the verbs that combine with them. The particle can, in its turn, take a
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 14
complement as well. This is what happens in sentences of the type in (29a), analysed in Den Dikken (1995) along the lines of (29b), with the book (the subject of the small clause whose predicate is on the shelf) moving optionally into the specifier position of the particle’s projection. (29) a. b.
put <the book> down <the book> on the shelf [VP V=put [PrtP <the book> Prt=down [SC <the book> [PP on the shelf]]]]
The point that is important for our discussion of the IPP effect is that particles (according to Den Dikken 1995) are heads of phrases that serve as the immediate complement of the verbs that select them, and that they can themselves take a complement as well. When we now return to (25) and recall that ge-, the participial prefix, is in complementary distribution with incorporated particles, we are led to the hypothesis that ge- occupies the head of a particle phrase in the immediate complement of the verb: (30)
[VP V=leven [PrtP Prt={ge-, her-, over-}]]
Now, when a verb that combines with ge- in turn combines with a projection of a lower verb, this projection needs to be accommodated as the complement of ge-, as in (31) (where the numbers match those in the schema in (18)): (31) * [VP2 V2PTC [PrtP Prt=ge- [VP3 V3]]] The problem posed by (31) is that ge- interrupts the link between V3 and V2. V3 needs to be incorporated into the verbal cluster.9 The presence of the particle frustrates this: the non-verbal Prt in (31) structurally intervenes between V2 and V3, rendering direct incorporation of V3 into V2 impossible on pain of a locality violation (minimality); incorporating V3 into ge- on the way up to V2 is also out of the question because Prt is not a legitimate host for verb incorporation (verbs can incorporate only into verbs, not into particles). This failure to include V3 in the verbal cluster rules (31) ungrammatical. The ungrammaticality of (31) is what is at the heart of the IPP effect in Continental West-Germanic. In the schema in (18), the bare infinitive in the position of V3 must be incorporated into the verbal cluster; inserting the 9
In this short paper, I cannot discuss why verb cluster formation happens, nor can I go into detail regarding the syntax of verb cluster formation. This is a complex matter that has given rise to myriad different accounts over the decades. See Zwart (2011) and Broekhuis & Corver (2015) and references cited there.
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 15
particle ge- in between V2 and V3 makes this impossible, and hence any V2 selected by an auxiliary expecting a participial complement must forgo gewhenever it takes a bare infinitive as its complement. 4.2. VP-fronting and IPP in triverbal constructions with a bare-infinitival V3 When the projection of V2 is fronted, as in (10a), nothing changes in the picture sketched in the previous subsection. Once again, if ge- is present between V2PTC and V3, this blocks cluster formation. So when VP2 is fronted, IPP continues to be obligatory. But when what is fronted is VP3 rather than VP2, as in (9a), we do not get IPP. This is now easy to understand as well. When VP3 in (31) is spelt out in the left periphery, the exponent of V3 is not incorporated into the verbal cluster. The downstairs VP3 remains silent, and as a result the presence of gedoes not wreak havoc for verb-cluster formation. (32)
[VP3 V3] … [VP2 V2PTC [PrtP Prt=ge- [VP3 V3]]]
The syntax of past participles in Continental West-Germanic languages that have ge- in their lexica features a PrtP headed by ge- in the participle’s complement whenever possible. Since nothing obstructs the presence of ge- in the complement of participial V2 in (32), the output of (32) will be picked over and above a structure in which V2PTC takes VP3 directly as its complement (i.e., an IPP structure). The result, as desired, is that IPP is illicit in (9a). 4.3. IPP in the passive voice In passive (12), IPP is just as obligatory as it is in its active counterpart in (11). This is exactly what the analysis of the morphosyntax of the IPP effect presented here predicts. In the passive, we once again have an auxiliary selecting a participial complement as V1, and V2PTC again has a projection of a bare infinitive in its complement. For exactly the same reason as in the case of active (11), the particle ge- must remain absent in the periphrastic passive in (12). With geand its concomitant PrtP left out from the syntactic structure, the syntax lands on its feet, delivering the IPP version of (12). This now gives us a complete account for the explananda in ➀.10 10 Note that the proposal regarding IPP presented in section 4 is compatible with Baker, Johnson & Roberts’ (1989) analysis of the passive, according to which the external θ-role in the passive is assigned to the participial morpheme (‘PM’). In my analysis of the morphosyntax of IPP, V2 in (18)
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 16
4.4. A postlude on ‘infinitival passives’ At the end of this section, let me highlight an ingredient of examples of the type in (11a) (repeated below as (33a), along with a second instance of the same type) that I have not had occasion to talk about so far. A closer look at the Dutch sentences in (33) reveals that there are in fact two unusual infinitives here: not only is laten ‘let’ showing up unexpectedly as an infinitive, the most deeply embedded verb (lezen ‘read’ and repareren ‘fix’) is also an infinitive (sometimes called an ‘infinitival passive’), whereas in English it can only be a past participle (see (34)). (33) a. ze they b. ze they
hebben have hebben have
het the de the
boek laten/*gelaten lezen book let.IPP/let.PTC read.INF auto laten/*gelaten repareren car let.IPP/let.PTC fix.INF
(= (11a))
they have had the car fixed (34) a. b. * they have have the car fixed c. * they have had the car fix d. * they have have the car fix These facts raise two questions: (i) is the most deeply embedded infinitive in the Dutch examples in (33) a case of IPP, and (ii) why does English resist an infinitive under causative have in (34)? The answer to the first question is straightforwardly negative. In the analysis of the Continental West-Germanic IPP effect given earlier in this section, the role of verb cluster formation is crucial. The forced absence of geis a consequence of forced incorporation of V3 into the verbal cluster in the schema in (18): ge- blocks incorporation of V3 into V2. But nothing syntactically prevents V3 from taking the particle ge- as its complement. So it should be perfectly legitimate in syntax for V3 to be a particle. The fact that V3 in (33) is an infinitive is thus not a case of IPP. From an Anglocentric perspective it is nonetheless surprising to see an is a participle. The composition of participial morphology in Dutch is bipartite, consisting of a prefixal particle syntactically occupying the complement-of-V position (ge-) and an inflectional suffix that originates in a functional head above the participial verb (which in (28) I labelled ‘Asp’), whose allomorphs are the regular alveolar suffix -d/-t and a suffix syncretic with the infinitival suffix, -en. In IPP contexts, the particle portion of the participial composite is forced to be absent (ge- cannot be included because its presence would preclude verb-cluster formation between V2 and V3); but the suffixal portion is present, and spelt out by the allomorph -en. It is this latter portion of the IPP form that could continue to be held responsible for absorbing the external θ-role in the passive.
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 17
infinitive here — an infinitive with a passive interpretation, or ‘infinitival passive’. English, as we saw in (34), does not allow this at all. It is tempting to attribute this contrast between Dutch and English to the fact that the former has an infinitival suffix (-en) whereas the latter conspicuously lacks one. If we follow Baker, Johnson & Roberts (1989) and assume that in the passive the external is being assigned to an inflectional morpheme (see fn. 10 for some elaboration), we could capitalise on the presence of explicit infinitival morphology in Dutch (33) by saying that it is this morpheme that ‘absorbs’ the external θ-role here. And such a treatment of (33) could then shed light on the ungrammaticality of English *they had the car fix as well, in light of the fact that English lacks an infinitival suffix. Such an approach would amount to a literal interpretation of the term ‘infinitival passive’. But the idea that the Dutch infinitival suffix -en can ‘stand in for’ the participial morpheme as a recipient of the external θ-role in the passive is not tenable. An insuperable problem for such an approach is the grammaticality of (35b), which cannot involve infinitival passivisation because weten ‘know’ does not support passivisation or, for that matter, any kind of valency reduction: see (36).11 (35) a.
ik heb ze de uitslag laten weten I have them the result let.INF know.INF
11 Arguably, the syntax of the infinitives in (35b) and (33) is active, featuring an implicit subject. The fact that Dutch allows an implicit subject in constructions of the type in (35b) (and, by the same token, in (33)) whereas English does not can plausibly be related to another known difference between Dutch and English in the realm of implicit subjects — the one seen in (i) (where toestaan ‘PRT.stand’ is one of the Dutch translation equivalents for English permit. Some attested examples of the type in (ib) are given in (ii).
(i) a. b.
(ii) a. b. c. d. e.
this allows/permits/invites *(us) to conclude that S dit rechtvaardigt (ons) te concluderen dat S this justifies us to conclude that S dit staat (ons) toe te concluderen dat S this stands us PRT to conclude that S dit nodigt (ons) uit te concluderen dat S this invites us to conclude that S er is geen enkele aanwijzing die het rechtvaardigt te concluderen dat S there is no single indication that it justifies to conclude that S de grote respons (90%) staat toe te concluderen dat S the big response 90% stands PRT to conclude that S dit staat toe te ontspannen this stands PRT to relax het staat toe te communiceren met een bezoeker it stands PRT to communicate with a visitor het staat toe te controleren voor welke objecten de manager is gecreëerd it stands PRT to check for which objects the manager is created
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 18
b.
‘I have let them know the result’ ik heb de uitslag laten weten I have the result let.INF know.INF ‘I made the result known’
(36) a. * dit wordt (door iedereen/niemand) geweten this is by everyone/nobody known ‘this is known by everyone/nobody’ b. * dit weet gemakkelijk cf. * dit ziet gemakkelijk this knows easily this sees easily c. * dit laat zich weten dit laat zich zien this lets REFL know this lets REFL see So the most deeply embedded verb in (33) is neither an IPP form nor an ‘infinitival passive’.12
5. The te-infinitival cases What is left to account for is the cluster of explananda in ➁, involving teinfinitival tokens of V3 in the schema in (19), repeated below. (19)
[V1=AUX [V2 [te V3]]]
In the active, the schema in (19) factors out into three separate syntactic structures, one involving verb clustering, a second featuring extraposition of [te V3] (a full CP in this case), and the third, the so-called ‘third construction’ (Den Besten et al. 1988), being a combination of extraposition and scrambling of non-verbal material contained in the projection of V3. As (37) shows, only the first of these patterns gives rise to IPP. (37) a. ik heb het boek proberen te lezen [verb clustering] I have the book try. IPP to read.INF b. ik heb geprobeerd het boek te lezen [CP extraposition] I have try.PTC the book to read.INF c. ik heb het boek geprobeerd te lezen [‘third construction’] I have the book try.PTC to read.INF all: ‘I have tried to read the book’ 12 There are other reasons as well that lead me to reject Baker, Johnson & Roberts’ (1989) analysis of the passive in terms of a θ-role absorbing inflectional affix. I refer readers interested in these reasons to Den Dikken (to appear) and Collins (2005).
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 19
Note that (37a) and (37c) have the same word order, differing only with respect to the form of V2. The fact that (37a) (involving verb clustering) and (37b) (the ‘third construction’) co-exist leads to the impression that IPP is optional in (19). But when we tease (37a) and (37c) apart in syntax, the conclusion that emerges is that IPP is in fact categorical, and occurs only in verb clustering contexts. For the verb clustering case in (37a), nothing needs to be said in addition to what I already said about the schema in (18) in section 4. The IPP form is obligatory here because of the fact that the presence of ge- precludes verb clustering. The reason why in the CP extraposition case in (37b) no IPP effect emerges is plain as well: with the constituent [te V3] in extraposition, no verb clustering obtains, so ge- is legitimate, and we had already seen in section 4 that ge- is obligatory whenever it is allowed to occur in the complement of a participial verb. The ‘third construction’ is syntactically very much like (38b), so it, too, features the participial form of V2 rather than the IPP form. No further discussion of the active forms of the schema in (19) is needed. But the passive forms of this schema do call for some more discussion. Recall that here, we see a prohibition on the IPP form not observed in the passive of the schema in (18). The relevant example from section 1.2 is (14), repeated below as (38): (38) % het boek is geprobeerd/*proberen te lezen (= (14)) the book is try.PTC/try.IPP to read.INF ‘people tried to read the book’ The question posed by (38), viewed against the background of the discussion of (37), is why passivisation of (19) blocks verb clustering. An answer suggests itself when we delve a little more deeply into the properties of Dutch ‘long passives’. From (39a), it is clear that we are dealing in (12a) with a personal passive in which the internal argument of the most deeply embedded verb is treated as the subject of the clause: this argument agrees in number with the finite auxiliary. In (39b), by contrast, plural agreement between zijn and de boeken is impossible: (39b) is sharply worse than (38), regardless of the choice of form for V2 (see also Zwart 2015; Wurmbrand 2001:19 reports that plural agreement is grammatical in corresponding German examples). (39) a. % de boeken zijn laten/*gelaten lezen the books are let.IPP/let.PTC read.INF b. * de boeken zijn geprobeerd/proberen te lezen
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 20
the books
are
try.PTC/try.IPP
to read.INF
This suggests that (38) is not a personal passive but instead an impersonal one, not featuring promotion of an argument to subject and not involving an Agree relation between the finite verb and a referential noun phrase. That this conclusion is correct is further confirmed by the contrast between the examples in (40a) and (40b): (40) a. er zijn (*de) boeken gelezen there are the books read.PTC ‘people have read books’ b. er is/*zijn geprobeerd (de) boeken te lezen there is/are tried.PTC a/the books to read.INF ‘people have tried to read (the) books’ In (40a), boeken ‘books’ is the associate of the expletive er, agreeing with the finite auxiliary and showing the familiar definiteness restriction. In (40b), by contrast, boeken cannot agree with the auxiliary, which is invariably in the third person singular form, and no definiteness effect manifests itself. So in (40b) the internal argument of the most deeply embedded verb is not promoted to subject at any point in the derivation. The passive in (40b) is an impersonal passive, with the infinitival clause (de) boeken te lezen ‘to read (the) books’ as the associate of the expletive er. In (38), het boek has been topicalised out of the infinitival clause; it cannot become the subject of the matrix clause. The fact that in the passive of the schema in (19) er takes as its associate the entire infinitival clause, in an impersonal passive, entails that the infinitival clause is necessarily in extraposition in such passives. This in turn means that no verb-cluster formation takes place. And this directly explains the fact that no IPP occurs: IPP is exclusively the province of verb clustering constructions, as explained by the analysis of Continental West-Germanic IPP presented in section 4. For our purposes in this paper, this is sufficient when it comes to accounting for the cluster of explananda in ➁. The active/passive dichotomy in the distribution of IPP in constructions of the type in (19) is a reflex of the fact that personal passivisation of such constructions is impossible in Dutch. The question of why personal passivisation of (19) fails is a topic for another paper. References Baker, Mark, Kyle Johnson & Ian Roberts. 1989. Passive arguments raised. Linguistic Inquiry 20. 219–51.
Infinitivus pro participio, active versus passive 21 Besten, Hans den, Jean Rutten, Tonjes Veenstra & Joop Veld. 1988. Verb raising, extrapositie en de derde constructie. Ms., University of Amsterdam, Dept. of General Linguistics. Breul, Carsten. 2014. The perfect participle paradox: Some implications for the architecture of grammar. English Language & Linguistics 18. 449–70. Broekhuis, Hans & Norvert Corver. 2015. Syntax of Dutch: Verbs and verb phrases (Vol. 2). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press. Collins, Chris. 2005a. A smuggling approach to the passive in English. Syntax 8. 81–120. Coopmans, Peter. 1985. Languages types: Continua or parameters? PhD dissertation, Utrecht University. Dikken, Marcel den. 1995. Particles: On the syntax of verb–particle, ditransitive and causative constructions. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. Dikken, Marcel den. 2003. When particles won’t part. Ms., CUNY Graduate Center. Dikken, Marcel den. to appear. Canonical and reverse predication in the syntax of the active/passive diathesis alternation. Ms., RIL/HAS & ELTE/SEAS. Emonds, Joseph. 1976. A transformational approach to English syntax. New York: Academic Press. Hoekstra, Eric & W. Taanman. 1995. Een Westfriese gradatie van het Infinitivus-proParticipio effect. Ms., Meertens Instituut, Amsterdam. Hoekstra, Teun, Monic Lansu & Marion Westerduin. 1987. Complexe verba. Glot 10. 61–77. Kayne, Richard. 2005. Movement and silence. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. Keyser, S. Jay & Thomas Roeper. 1992. Re: The abstract clitic hypothesis. Linguistic Inquiry 23. 89–125. Thoms, Gary & George Walkden 2018. vP-fronting with and without remnant movement. Journal of Linguistics (to appear). http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S002222671800004X Vanden Wyngaerd, Guido. 1994. IPP and the structure of participles. Groninger Arbeiten zur germanistischen Linguistik 37. 265–76. Wurmbrand, Susi. 2001. Infinitives: Restructuring and clause structure. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter. 1993. Dutch syntax: A minimalist approach. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Groningen. Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter. 2011. The syntax of Dutch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Zwart, C. Jan-Wouter. 2015. Restructuring restructuring: Explaining long passive phenomena in Dutch. Paper presented at the Amsterdam/Leuven verb clusters workshop, Amsterdam, 29 May 2015. Marcel den Dikken Department of English Linguistics, Eötvös Loránd University Research Institute for Linguistics, Hungarian Academy of Sciences dmarcel@nytud.hu